“Self-consciousness exists in itself and for itself, in that, and by the fact that it exists for another self-consciousness; that is to say, it is only by being acknowledged or ‘recognized'” (Hegel, Phenomenology, Baillie trans., p. 229). Thus Hegel begins the “Self-Consciousness” division, which in the final version of his outline occupies the remainder of the book.
Looking forward, Harris comments “‘Recognition’ is the Concept of Spirit as such. We are going to observe the motion of this Concept which is a ‘multi-sided and multi-significant complexity'” (Hegel’s Ladder I, p. 344).
Its ethical destiny is to become mutual recognition, but it begins as a deformed self-will. “We must realize that we are concerned with the pure self-will that has been communally designated as ‘original sin’, and that will typically designate itself as absolute virtue or duty (because it cannot have any other social justification)” (p. 353).
“When I recognize what I want to be in someone else, then I have ‘come out of myself’. The attraction (which is all that was attended to in the desiring posture) reveals itself first to be ‘self-repulsion’. The self that I presently am, I do not want. I have lost myself. Empirically I could be in despair. Those who recognize their ideal self in another sometimes are in despair. But logically the other side of the truth is more dangerous. As the object of my desire, what I see out there is not another independent self, but only a passive essence waiting for me to take possession of it. Actually, however, my relationship with that other self is more complicated. The self I want to emulate is not simply an object. She has to make herself into an object for my sake. If I am to know how to achieve what I want, she must help me, she must negate herself willingly and be at my disposal. But she may not see herself as the self that I see; or she may not want to be that. Above all, she may not want to help me to become that self” (p. 345).
Hegel famously discusses a life-and-death struggle that leads to servitude. The experience of servitude, however, will turn out to contain a vital key to further development. Labor provides a concrete model not only for the “constructive” role of the mind in interpreting things and the various practical constraints on doing this well, but also for the acquisition of skills, and for work on oneself.
In Harris’ words, “Serfdom reduces the free human agent to a thing. The serf himself is property for the free self-consciousness of his lord…. In place of the one thing and its many properties we have the one free self and his many serfs.”
“But there is a much more significant inversion of Perception here. Perception ‘takes the truth from things’ as they are given. But the human thing makes the truth of things, by controlling their properties. Serfdom is a new relation of the perceiving mind to its truth…. The lord turns the serf into a thing; but then in his labor the serf turns himself into a made thing. He trains himself into the shape of the practical Understanding” (p. 366).
“The [being-for-self] of the serf is different from that of the lord, because it is incorporated in his body — a laboring instrument which has ‘independent being’ for him. The being-for-self of the lord is just his commanding voice” (ibid).
“Through the laboring activity pure being-for-self comes to be a subsisting thing” (p. 367).
“Hegel’s reason for holding that the fear of death is essential to the right comprehension of the cycle at its finite climax is now fairly easy to graph, even if we do not find it convincing. Without the daily piecemeal discipline of obedience, the serf would never come to regard everything he touches as belonging to the lord and hence requiring to be treated with absolute respect…. If the sheep were his own, then his private interest, which Hegel calls ‘a vain sense of one’s own’, would have to be dominant. The discipline of service creates ultimately the recognition that the object has its own good, its own sense” (p. 369).
“And even if the Hellenic (or more precisely the Platonic) conviction abides with us — the conviction that spontaneous ‘desire’ can be developed into ever higher degrees of ‘love’, and that love not fear is the true road to practical objectivity — still we cannot deny that the ‘fear of the Lord’ (both the earthly and the heavenly Judge) has in fact been crucial to the evolution of our presently more fraternal (but how feebly effective) value-consciousness” (p. 370).
I think it’s also worth noting implications of this second beginning. Hegel’s approach is clearly developmental and in that sense “historical”, but it clearly does not follow a linear path that could correspond to a single progression in time. We just completed an arc from simple sensation to mathematical physics, and now we are beginning a new ethical arc, starting from the quasi-mythical origin of lordship and servitude.
On the other hand, I think Hegel actually thinks real human consciousness is always already self-consciousness, and actually considers the separate treatment of mere “consciousness” to be artificial. The ethical part of the book covers his main intent; the whole previous arc was a kind of preamble.